How Should We Study the Nexus of Architecture
and Mathematics? |
EDITOR'S NOTE. While preparing
the Call for Papers for the sixth Nexus conference on architecture
and mathematics, I examined the Nexus archives to verify, within
Nexus, what subjects had been discussed at length and what was
missing. It became clear from this examination that Nexus contributions
contain not only a wide variety of subject matter, but a wide
variety of methods of study as well. In order to try begin a
dialogue about methodology (a topic that was touched on during
the Round Table discussion at Nexus 2000 in Ferrara), I solicited
comments from two scholars in different fields on the paper presented
at the first Nexus conference in Fucecchio in 1996 by John Clagett
entitled "Transformational
Geometry and the Central European Baroque Church." Dr.
David Speiser, physicist, who has followed Nexus since its
inception, and Dr. Sandro Caparrini, historian of mathematics
and newcomer to Nexus, bring not only different disciplinary
points of view to the subject but who have different experiences
of the Nexus community. The polemic that follows is in no way
intended as a personal criticism of Clagett, but rather a discussion
of method and the degree of rigor that should be expected from
Nexus contributions. Further comments from readers of the Nexus
Network Journal who wish to contribute to this dialogue are
welcome. Kim
Williams
SANDRO CAPARRINI WROTE: The subject
of the article is truly a particular one. Clagett proposes to
find the relationships between the architecture of the Baroque
churches of Central Europe and "transformational geometry".
It should be noted that Clagett does not seek generic links between
the Baroque and mathematics, but between a certain type of Baroque
and a particular branch of geometry. There is no doubt that there are in some way connections between some
aspects of Baroque architecture and the mathematics of that time:
Guarini was a mathematician; Wren was a mathematical physicist
of some renown; Desargues discovered projective geometry as a
result of his work as an architect. However, it seems to me that
Clagett's paper discusses significant problems without taking
the first step towards their resolution.
It would be necessary to review the paper line by line in
order to give substance to this criticism. I think however that
it can be briefly summed up in two points:
1. Clagett cites precise mathematical theories while
using a language that is incredibly vague. This leads him often
into error, as when, for example, he confuses different theories.
Let us look at some examples. What exactly is meant by the
statement, "during this time, reasoning shifted from the
isolated to the integrated" (p. 38)? Almost nothing; it
is a statement that could be applied to any scientific theory
that assembles and corrects knowledge that was previously scattered.
The phrase, "in Newton's Principia (1687) the phenomena
of dynamics was [sic] so lucidly formulated that the physical
world was redefined through motion" (p. 38) demonstrates
that Clagett has only second-hand knowledge of the Principia,
since in that treatise the results are expressed in a difficult,
concise, obscure way, a far cry from the clarity of modern manuals
and almost impossible for readers of the time to comprehend (and,
for that matter, for readers of our own day as well).
The truly troubling point, central to the discourse as a whole,
comes when the paper deals with "transformational geometry".
In the history of mathematics, the theory of transformation is
a precise point of view that goes back to the second half of
the 1800s, and whose general formulation was first given by Felix
Klein in 1872. Citing Euclid's demonstration of the Pythagorean
theorem in this context shows that Clagett has a weak grasp of
the material. There is no doubt that he intends a reference to
the theory of groups of transformation, since he talks constantly
of rotations, translations, reflections, and other transformations
of the plane.
Besides being vague, Clagett's style is often contorted. A sentence
such as "This effect of oscillating proximity resulted from
an intention to create a spectrum of elements eternally approaching
singularity; to establish a dynamic continuum" (p. 38) subjects
the reader to a couple of minutes of mental torture before he
is able to extract some hint of meaning. Here the use of scientific
terms ("oscillating", "spectrum", "singularity",
"dynamic continuum") is superimposed on a language
worthy of the worst art critic. Barba non facit philosophum;
a few technical terms are not sufficient to demonstrate that
one knows mathematics. The term "approaching singularity"
must hold a special fascination for Clagett, because he returns
to it at the article's end (p. 50). By closing one's eyes and
concentrating a bit it is almost possible to visualize this "approaching
singularity"; it is an image worthy of Poe or Kafka.
2. The connection between mathematical developments
and architectural innovations are never proven in any way, shape,
or form. There are no citations of notes, letters, or other writings
that make evident these connections. In effect, Clagett limits
himself to setting two arguments, the mathematical and the architectural,
side-by-side, without making them interact in any way. Thus,
it becomes possible to prove anything one wished, and in fact,
this method is often used in texts of scant scientific value,
such as specious New Age works that "demonstrate",
for instance, that the Maya and the Egyptians were in contact
(both cultures built pyramids).
Let us take an example. Close to the beginning of the article
is set forth a table which, according to Clagett, serves to place
the Central European Baroque church in the context of the mathematical
development of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries:
Mathematical and Architectural Developments: A comparative
Chronology, 1639-1827
Desargues: Brouillon projet |
1639 |
|
Descartes: La Géometrie |
1673 |
|
Leibniz's first paper on the calculus |
1684 |
G. Dientzenhofer: Pilgrimage church at Kappel begins construction |
Newton Principia |
1687 |
Approximate start of the Central European Baroque church |
|
1694 |
Fischer v. Erlach: Project for Dreifaltigkeitskirche |
|
1713 |
C. Dientzenhofer: Smirice, chapel |
Taylor: Methodus incrementorum |
1715 |
|
|
1726 |
J. Dientzenhofer: Holzkirchen |
Saccheri: Euclid Vindicated |
1733 |
Neumann: Würzburg, Hofkirche |
|
1737 |
Guarini: Architettura civile |
D'Alembert: Traité de dynamique |
1743 |
|
|
1744 |
J.M. Fischer: St. Michaelskirche |
Euler: Introductio |
1748 |
|
|
1763 |
Neumann: Vierzehnheiligen |
John Love: Geodesia |
1768 |
|
Hyperbolic trigonometry |
1770 |
Approximate close of the Central European Baroque church |
Lobachevskian geometry |
1827 |
|
What can be deduced from this table? Absolutely nothing. There
is no relation whatsoever between the Methodus incrementorum
of B. Taylor (1715) and the churches of C. Dietzenhofer.
Effectively a table such as this could prove a thesis that is
the exact opposite of Clagett's: there are no relationships at
all between Baroque architecture and mathematics; the two disciplines
appear as far from each other as the works of Shakespeare and
the development of statistics.
If Clagett wished to demonstrate, for example, that a given
architect of the 1600s was influenced by the Pantheon, no proof
would be necessary beyond stylistic resemblances. The importance
and notoriety of the model would be in itself sufficient proof.
The situation changes when it is necessary to demonstrate that
a given architect took as his point of departure the most abstract
mathematics of his day: in this case it is necessary to find
direct connections. Are there letters in which the architect
in question declares that he has read a certain book? Do we know
if he was actively engaged in mathematics, or if he was in contact
with mathematicians? In the case of Thomas Jefferson, for example,
it is known that he had in his library various texts of higher
mathematics. If we were to find in Monticello specific geometric
coincidences then we would be justified in deducing that these
are not chance occurrences. These are the methods with which
history is written.
I don't see any particular signs of the influence of higher
mathematics in the architecture that is discussed by Clagett.
He speculates, for example, that the attempt to make squares
and circles coincide derives from the problem of the quadrature
of the circle (p. 41). In reality, there are no necessary connections
between these two forms: every high school student can draw circles
in squares and squares in circles without wanting the prove any
theorem by doing so. More generally, the use of circles, squares,
and ellipses arranged in various ways doesn't indicate a knowledge
of higher mathematics. It is obvious that particular symmetries
exist in Baroque architecture: a good portion of art has to do
with symmetry (or its absence). There are certainly examples
of figures that are rotated or deformed in Baroque decoration,
derived almost certainly from the artist's need to give movement
and variety to architecture elements used thousands of times
before. Is it possible to see how this phenomenon is connected
to Descartes's Géométrie of 1637 of or to
Desargues's Brouillon projet of 1639?
A last note on Clagett's weak thesis is shown on p. 49, on
which is discussed the influence of Desargues's projective geometry
on architecture. The works cited go from 1580 to 1766, and thus
show how Clagett confounds the study of perspective, which goes
back at least as far as Masaccio, with the mathematic discipline
known as projective geometry (and perhaps the descriptive geometry
of G. Monge as well). Those who wish to know the details
on the diffusion of perspective and the methods used to study
it should consult The Science of Art: Optical Themes
in Western Art From Brunelleschi to Seurat by
Martin Kemp (1990). It is a work rich in precise facts,
that shows how a paper of this type should be written.
As the above arguments show, my critique
concentrates on two principle points, and this makes Clagett's
ideas appear to be better defined than they actually are. In
fact they are often so imprecise that it is difficult to analyze
them. This is in fact the main weakness of the paper: it is not
possible to say that Clagett has given even the slightest demonstration
of a possible connection between Baroque architecture and advanced
mathematics.
DAVID SPEISER REPLIED: Kim
Williams, the Spiritus Rector of the Nexus conferences,
had told me that John Clagett's paper on the "Transformational
Geometry and the Central European Baroque Church", published
in the first book, Nexus: Architecture and Mathematics
(1996), had been criticised by Sandro Caparrini. As I myself
had retained a good impression of this contribution, which I
had found stimulating at the Nexus 1996 conference in Fuccechio,
I expressed my surprise. Upon reading Caparrini's critique and
then twice re-reading Clagett's article, I had to admit that
Caparrini's critique, as far as it goes, is justified. But I
think that he does not sufficiently take into account that the
Baroque is a style particularly difficult to investigate and
to analyze, especially from the Nexus Architecture-Mathematics
point of view.
And furthermore, I say, one has to take into account that
while, due to the lack of precise mathematical notions, Clagett's
views are not solidly enough grounded in the architecture side
of the Nexus, his remarks, nevertheless, seem to me stimulating
for further research, and to point in fruitful and promising
directions. Whereupon the Spiritus Rector invited me to
write a short summary of my ideas. In what follows, I review
by referring to a few examples of some of Clagetts views, appreciating
and criticising them, but always from the Nexus Architecture-Mathematics
point of view. For this reason and for not being too boringly
repetitious, I refer to the two pillars of Nexus simply by the
letters A and M.
One must consider, that most, if not all, concrete AM confrontations
-- and the same holds even more so for the really established
AM connections -- refer to either Greek, Roman, Romanesque, or
Renaissance buildings, and sometimes also to modern ones. But
rarely has there been a penetrating AM study of a Gothic or a
Baroque building, especially of one that presents most of the
characteristics of either of these two styles. The reason for
this is obviously that the Gothic e and the Baroque styles present
a more complex and difficult situation for AM research. Therefore
AM investigations on either of these styles must always be considered
as pioneer work; assertions in a direction that promise to be
fruitful are meritorious, and in spite of their shortcomings
and the criticism they deserve, must be welcomed by students
of the Nexus-AM. And indeed, among the numerous points made by
John Clagett, there are many that do point in a possibly fruitful
direction for further research, and may even guide future studies
to something more.
In the following I shall discuss a few examples.
- Baroque architects often tried to hide the geometric calculus,
which underlies the plan of a building already before the details
are worked out. This, I guess, was a reaction to the ideal of
clarity and transparency that guided the great renaissance artists.
And this is probably what Clagett has in mind, when he says "Yet
Neumann's section.... ; as if Neumann once again shifted the
layers of the chapels plan" (pp. 45-46). This deliberate
hiding of the basic geometric idea is one reason that makes it
so difficult to grasp the "geometric calculus" behind
baroque buildings.
- But then Clagett also points to another important characteristic
of the baroque style, e.g. (p. 45) "the intersection of
geometric curves, surfaces, and figures, such as circles, squares,
octagones, cupolas, etc. In the Romanesque and Renaissance styles,
these geometric figures are presented as beautiful in themselves,
each one contributing individually to the desired beauty and
harmony of the building. But Baroque architecture is not satisfied
by this "individual presentation," favouring M-constructions
of "interpenetrating" curves, surfaces and 3-dimensional
bodies, all chosen from a great variety. It is through the well-thought-out
interplay of these M-elements that the architect expresses his
ideas. This is an important point, even if Clagett does not sufficiently
analyse the mathematics used in each case. However, for a student
it is a useful starting point for penetrating into the puzzles
presented by the Baroque style.
- The same must be said about his " five intersecting
quasi-ellipsoidal domes" (p. 45), also something deeply
characteristic for the Baroque style, where A makes quite important
use of M. But then, what exactly is "quasi-ellipsoidal"
? After his conference I had myself a very interesting conversation
with Clagett, during which he told me that the presumed ellipses
observed in architecture are often in fact "ovals".
Ovals, contrary to ellipses, are not curves defined by one law
only, but are put together from several arcs of circles in a
"smooth" way such that the tangent to the curve never
changes abruptly, but always continuously: an oval has no corners.
But when much later I showed Sylvie Duvernoy's very interesting
paper on arenas from the Nexus 2002 conference in Obidos, "Architecture and Mathematics
in Roman Amphitheaters" to my friend, mathematician
B. Marzetta, he discovered and proved that any ellipse can be
approximated as closely as one wishes by an oval and vice versa.
This, of course, puts many often-made statements, whether on
the Roman or the Baroque style, into question! Whether for 3-dimensional
ellipsoids an analogue statement holds, i.e., whether there are
"ovaloids", I do not know. A three-dimensional ovaloid
could be generated through the rotation of an ordinary two-dimensional
oval around its major axis of symmetry. Cutting this ovaloid
in two by means of a horizontal plane of symmetry, the upper
part may serve as the cover of a Baroque church. A possible candidate
for this, among many others, is Borromini's S. Carlo alle Quattro
Fontane in Rome.
This situation presents a series of interesting questions and
problems for Nexus research, which range from measurement techniques,
through stylistic investigations of historic buildings, up to
aesthetic theories on Baroque art.
- I must admit that the meaning of the term Zweischaligkeit,
literally "bi-shelledness" (p. 48), borrowed from the
German, did not become clear to me; neither did I understand
to what exactly in the building it refers, nor what in general
its aim and function in Baroque architecture are.
- Clagett uses explicitly the term Gesamtkunstwerk (
p. 37), which was coined by R. Wagner who introduced it into
his theory of the Musikdrama. Here Clagett makes a very
fortunate point. That the Baroque style artistically combined
architecture, sculpture, painting, and especially the art of
decoration to a degree not ever seen in Europe before or since,
was, of course often noted. But I wonder, whether the full importance
of the ambition of the Baroque Gesamtkunstwerk was always
grasped sufficiently and seriously enough. For here we probably
find the highest ambition of the Baroque art, and this too is
an open field for all kinds of Nexus research.
- It is curious that Clagett does not mention at all the "artificial
architectures" created in so many Baroque churches and palaces,
together with the sister-art painting, and, of course, also with
the sister-art M, namely, the understanding of the rules of perspective.
This heralds a first, of course only intuitive, understanding
of projective geometry. The first example of such an artificial
architecture, extending and covering the built one, may be Michelangelo's
ceiling of the Sistine Chapel, and the most virtuoso performance
is probably Pozzo's ceiling in San Ignazio in Rome. Later we
find, of course, many such painted extensions in Austrian and
South German churches and palaces as well. Incidentally, when
one manages to see and appreciate the built and the painted architecture
as one single building, one realizes that one criticism often
made of Baroque art is unjust: Baroque decorations, which are
often felt to be overloaded and even bombastic, will be appreciated
according to their just value if one realizes that they belong
to one building only, which is, however, about twice as high
as the purely architectural structure!
These examples shows, I think, where the merits of Clagett's
stimulating conference as well as its weaknesses lie. He points
to quite a few, important characteristics of Baroque architecture
and style, and they are a good starting point for Nexus reflections
as well as for concrete AM- research, but indeed, much remains
to be done! For, unfortunately, and this holds especially for
the end of the article, the respective roles of A and especially
M as well as their meeting points, i.e. the Nexus are not precisely
enough analyzed and worked out. While he leads our attention
to many an interesting question, his somewhat cavalier attitude
to mathematical vocabulary and theorems, suggest to the reader
often another answer to it.
ABOUT THE AUTHORS Sandro Caparrini
was born in Rapallo (Genova) in 1963,
and resides near Turin. He holds degrees in physics and mathematics.
He is a historian of mathematics, with a special interest in
the history of mechanics. He was recently awarded, for his essay
entitled "Early Theories of Vectors," the 2003
Slade Prize of the British Society for the History of Science,
presented biennially to the writer of an essay that makes a critical
contribution to the history of science.
David
Speiser is Professor Emeritus at the
Catholic University of Louvain, where he taught physics and mathematics
from 1963 to 1990. His research concerned elementary particles
and physical mathematics. He has been giving lectures and seminars
regularly at the Scuola Normale di Pisa since 1990. Since 1980,
he is the general editor of the complete works of the mathematicians
and physicists of the Bernoulli family. His work on the history
of science includes various publications, some of which are related
to art history. He presented "The
Symmetries of the Leaning Tower and the Baptistery of Pisa"
at Nexus '96, now available in Nexus: Architecture and Mathematics (1996).
The correct citation for
this article is: Sandro
Caparrini and David Speiser, "How Should We Study the Nexus
of Architecture and Mathematics", Nexus Network Journal,
vol. 6 no. 2 (Autumn 2004), http://www.nexusjournal.com/CapSpe.html |
top of
page
Copyright ©2004 Kim Williams
Books |
NNJ Homepage
NNJ
Editorial Board
Autumn
2004 Index
About the
Authors
Order
Nexus books!
Research
Articles
The
Geometer's Angle
Didactics
Book
Reviews
Conference and Exhibit Reports
Readers'
Queries
The Virtual Library
Submission Guidelines
Top
of Page |